The plot of Samuel Beckett’s Watt is simple enough: an
aimless man called Watt stumbles upon an estate in the Irish countryside,
becomes the butler for the estate’s owner (Mr. Knott), and generally loses his
mind (see previous posts). Beckett wrote the novel while hiding from Nazi
forces in occupied France, and years after its publication dismissed the novel
as “an exercise” that allowed him “to keep in touch.” This dismissal has had a
serious impact on the novel’s critical history, and lead many critics to agree
that the novel presents not so much characters in a plot but various linguistic
permutations that eventually empty language of meaning. I would argue, however,
especially in light of Derrida’s “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of
the Human Sciences,” that this dismissal of the novel as a linguistic exercise
actually highlights the fact that the novel itself dramatizes the play and
deferral of significatory systems. Thus we no longer see the emptiness of Watt
and Mr. Knott as a failure of characterization on Beckett’s part, but as the necessary
condition for understanding how meaning is made in any system.
I have already discussed Watt’s
dismay at watching the “Galls father and son” fix a piano (you may think I am
making a big deal out of one passage from a novel but it is almost the only
concrete event that happens in the whole novel). The fallout from this event
is, for Watt, the complete failure of signification. We see this dramatized
most especially with language, such as in the instance of Watt and the pot (get
it? “Watt” rhymes with “pot” rhymes with “Mr. Knott”). The narrator explains
that the pot
resembled a pot, it was
almost a pot, but it was not a pot of which one could say, Pot, pot, and
be comforted. It was in vain
that it answered, with unexceptionable adequacy, all the purposes,
and performed all the offices,
of a pot, it was not a pot. And it was just this hairbreadth departure from the
nature of a true pot that so excruciated Watt. (64-65)
Here the arbitrary nature of language comes to the
foreground, and Watt is characterized as a lamentably “deep subject” who mourns
the “hairbreadth departure from the nature of a true pot.” His need for stable
signification, or, as it is later characterized, “semantic succour,” is “so great
that he would set to trying names on things, and on himself, almost as a woman
hats. Thus of the pseudo-pot he would say, after reflection, It is a shield,
or, growing bolder, It is a raven, and so on” (66). Here, Watt cares not so much
for “true” signification as much as any signification at all—indeed, we learn
later that this disorienting experience in interstitial spaces (see “Beckett’s
Radical Ecology” from last week) actually allows Watt to enjoy the experience
of nothingness. The narrator explains that Watt did not “[long] at all times
for this restoration, of things, and for himself, to their comparative innocuousness,”
but that “there were times when he felt a feeling closely resembling the feeling
of satisfaction, at his being so abandoned, by the last rats” (67).
This
transition from the need for “semantic succor” to “a feeling closely resembling
the feeling of satisfaction” seems to me to reflect a shift from Derrida’s “saddened,
negative, nostalgic, guilty,
Rousseauistic side of thinking” to the “Nietzschean affirmation, that is the joyous affirmation of…a world of signs
without fault, without truth, and without origin which is offered to an active
interpretation” (292). Indeed, Mr. Knott comes to stand in alternatively as the
elusive Transcendental Signified—that center that will bestow meaning and rein
in the play of elements in a system—and precisely as the “noncenter” to the
system, which opens the freeplay of language infinitely. The narrator explains
that “Watt suffered neither from the presence of Mr. Knott, nor from his
absence,” and that “this ataraxy covered the entire house-room, the
pleasure-garden, [and] the vegetable-garden” (170). Watt’s “ataraxy,” or “freedom
from mental disturbance” (thanks
wiktionary!) ultimately allows him to excuse himself from all systems of
meaning to the point of insanity—a final point which underlines the hesitant
tone of Derrida’s conclusion, which gestures at the “formless, mute, infant,
and terrifying form of monstrosity” (293) that is, in every sense, unimaginable
for those of us still trapped in the old metaphysics game.
Hi Kevin! I found your essay really engaging and interesting, so, essentially my comment may just be a nit-picky clarification. Anyhow, your conclusion left me wondering about the nature of Beckett's insanity and Derrida's envisioned breakdown of meaning/structure. Is Beckett's version of insanity total absence of all coherent thought and with it all systems of meaning? Does any new system of meaning (insane or otherwise) come into play?
ReplyDelete