In Malabou’s “You
Are Your Synapses,” the dialectic between the unconscious and the personality,
the neuronal and the mental, the brain and the self is under consideration. Malabou
uses the discoveries of neuroscience to explain and understand more abstract
conceptions of selfhood; taking this perhaps to an extreme, I would like to employ
her ideas about the translation of neuronal patterns into images and the
plasticity of the brain to contemplate Hawthorne’s “The Birthmark,” to the
extent that it is as a symbolic embodiment of these mental processes.
Certainly
when Malabou and Hawthorne were writing these works, the following argument was
never, ever, in consideration. Nonetheless, I will obstinately argue for a
reading in which the characters Aylmer and Georgiana in “The Birthmark”
represent the relationship between the brain and its projected images. As we
have seen before, Hawthorne allegorizes Aylmer as a human mind. When
considering Malabou’s articles and the fact that both Aylmer and Georgiana are “flat”
characters that are reciprocal foils for each other, I would argue that Aylmer
and Georgiana together form one human mind, in which Aylmer is the “brain” (neuronal)
and Georgiana is the “proto-self” (mental).
In
“You Are Your Synapses,” Malabou avers that mental patterns are transcribed
from neuronal patterns and are finally constructed as “images” (61). Here, the
relationship with the constructed “brain” of Aylmer and Georgiana in “The
Birthmark” becomes clearer. Hawthorne insists that Aylmer grows more and more
obsessed with removing his wife’s hand-shaped birthmark, and in fact more and
more afraid of the birthmark, because he associates it directly with the
impossibility of human perfection, or, the impossibility of immortality; it is
the “spectral Hand that wrote mortality” (1322). Thus Georgiana is reduced to a
mere projected image of mortality, the object represented by the brain’s
fixation on death. The connection is furthered in the fact that Aylmer’s gaze eventually
causes Georgiana’s birthmark to appear: “[the birthmark] needed but a glance,
with the peculiar expression that [Aylmer’s] face often wore, to change the
roses of her cheek into a deathlike paleness, amid which the Crimson Hand was
brought strongly out, like a bas-relief of ruby on the whitest marble” (1322). Malabou
explains that the translation of neural patterns to mental patterns (“images”)
involves a certain circuitry which demonstrates that the brain is “caught in
the act of representing its own changing state as it goes about representing
something else” (61). As Aylmer, the brain, represents his own preoccupation
with death onto Georgiana and her birthmark, the birthmark seems to have a life
of its own that, in appearing under Aylmer’s gaze, represents that
preoccupation back to Aylmer, as evidence for his “own changing state.”
Georgiana
as the image of a self obsessed with mortality thus communicates to the brain
(Aylmer) the necessity of succeeding in debunking his fears and allowing his
self to reform more healthfully. The urgency with which Aylmer works to concoct
his elixir clearly increases as the story progresses and as the birthmark shows
itself more and more frequently. In the end, Aylmer does create a potion that
removes the birthmark. Yet it kills Georgiana in the process. Malabou’s concept
of plasticity as it relates to self-fashioning now comes into play. She
explains that the construction of the self is “structured by the dialectical
play of the emergence and annihilation of form” (72). Though Aylmer initially
succeeds in overcoming his self-definition through fear of mortality by
removing Georgiana’s birthmark, this achievement is fallible and would
constitute the “flexible” self that Malabou posits as impossible. Georgiana’s
death indicates that a new proto-self could not exist without the “explosion”
(using Malabou’s terms) of the last one.
Yet
in the end, Hawthorne seems to suggest that these two selves could, possibly, have
coexisted: “had Aylmer reached a profounder wisdom, he need not thus have flung
away the happiness, which would have woven his mortal life of the self-same
texture with the celestial” (1332). Evidently here Hawthorne returns to his
religious lesson: that Aylmer’s fear of mortality would have been assuaged had
he accepted the immortal afterlife of a pious person. Nonetheless, in my
reading of Georgiana as the proto-self and Aylmer as the neuronal self, the possibility
for the coexistence of two represented selves perhaps challenges a conceptual
reading of Malabou’s dialectic of explosion and creation of identity.
Emma, I think I follow your argument here, although I have to say that you engage with some of the intricacies of the Malabou in a way that makes me realize how I haven't quite managed to wrap my head around it.
ReplyDeleteThat said, your argument made me wonder whether the role of Georgiana and the role of the birthmark could/should be conflated. You position Georgiana as the proto-self and not the birthmark, and yet it seems to be the birthmark and not Georgiana that constitutes Aylmer's "projected image of mortality." How does Aylmer differentiate between Georgiana and her birthmark? Does he see them as one and the same? Forgive me if this is something I've missed in your argument or if I'm misunderstanding you, but it seems like sometimes you're suggesting that Aylmer does conflate the two—that they act upon him in the same way—and sometimes you make a point of separating them, and I wonder if this part of your argument could be clarified.