In “Line and Surface,” Vilém
Flusser draws a strict distinction between “imaginal” and “conceptual”
thinking, as they are realized by images and written texts respectively. The
two media, he posits, impose a different “structure on thinking:” “we must
follow the written text if we want to get at its message, but in pictures we
may get the message first, and then try to decompose it” (23). Flusser explains
that “when we translate image into concept, we decompose the image—we analyze
it.” In doing so, he claims, we “throw…a conceptual point-net over the image,
and capture only such meanings as did not escape through the meshes of the net”
(28). The inadequacy of written lines, which “relate their symbols to their
meanings point by point,” to explaining surfaces, which “relate their symbols
to their meanings by two-dimensional contexts” (27-28), represents what Flusser
calls “the present crisis.” What Flusser fails to recognize, it seems, is the
possibility that written lines can be used in the service of “imaginal”
thinking—indeed, that language can ever be used to disrupt the teleological “history”
of the sentence and gesture toward new “structures of thinking.”
Such
a project plays out (of course) in Samuel Beckett’s Watt. For the sake of concision, I will focus only on the most
obvious example of the intersection of imaginal and conceptual thinking in the
novel, which occurs when Watt tries to articulate the strange effect that a
painting has on his thought process. Watt
describes the painting, which he finds in the room of his fellow servant,
Erskine, as follows:
A circle, obviously described by
a compass, and broken at its lowest point, occupied the middle foreground, of
this picture…In the eastern background appeared a point, or dot. The
circumference was black. The point was blue, but blue! The rest was white. How
the effect of perspective was obtained Watt did not know. But it was obtained…Watt
wondered how long it would be before the point and the circle entered together
upon the same plane. Or had they not done so already, or almost? And was it not
rather the circle that was in the background, and the point that was in the
foreground? (104)
Here Watt’s struggle to determine the foreground and the
background of the painting are clearly presented in “conceptual” (or written)
lines. This desire to translate the “conceptual” to the “imaginal” is taken to
its logical extreme (as are most things in Beckett), as Watt:
wondered what the artist had
intended to represent (Watt knew nothing about painting), a circle and its
centre in search of each other, or a circle and its centre in search of a
centre and a circle respectively, or a circle and its centre in search of
its centre and a circle respectively, or a circle and its centre in search of a
centre and its circle respectively, or a circle and its centre not its centre
in search of its centre and its circle respectively, or a circle and a centre
not its centre in search of a centre and a circle respectively, or a circle and
a centre not its centre in search of its centre and a circle respectively,
or a circle and a centre not its centre in search of a centre and its circle
respectively, in boundless space, in endless time (Watt knew nothing about physics),
and at the thought that it was perhaps this, a circle and a centre not its
centre in search of a centre and its circle respectively, in boundless space,
in endless time, then Watt’s eyes filled with tears that he could not stem, and
they flowed down his fluted cheeks unchecked, in a steady flow, refreshing him
greatly. (104-05)
Watt’s permutational logic, which is clearly composed of
written (conceptual) lines, seems to become a dizzying textual surface that
contains a different, “imaginal” thought. When Flusser posits that, in the
future, “first there will be an image of something, then there will be an
explanation of that image, and then there will be an image of that explanation”
(30), I immediately thought of the many long passages in Watt in which the permutational logic is taken to its extreme, as
in the passage above. I will spare you more examples (mostly because they are
painstaking to transcribe but also because they get progressively longer as the
novel goes on), but it seems that Beckett is effectively able to translate
conceptual (written) lines, which still retain their individual "histories" in
isolation, into a textual space that can best be grasped as an (imaginal)
surface—one whose content is grasped more fully at first glance than by
painstakingly reading each permutation.
I
wonder if Flusser’s essay (which describes poetry as an “articulation of linear
thought” (30)) fails to take into account a wide range of seemingly conceptual
content that is actually insisting to be understood with imaginal structures of thought.
Kevin! I wanted more of this! Damn John Marx and his 600 words. Your argument that Beckett is trying to move toward some textual intersection of imaginal and conceptual thought was really convincing to me, especially as I tried to read that excerpt and it started to feel like some kind of Magic Eye (remember those? Here, I googled it for you: http://tinyurl.com/cmbfw89 )
ReplyDeleteAnyway, I'm still wondering how to think of Beckett's attempt to describe that odd image I kept scrolling down to the bottom of the post to try and understand. Why does he first use conceptual thought to describe an image, and then move toward the imaginal thing which obviously doesn't really invoke the same image? How do the pictures you posted deviate from the understanding we get when we read that (somewhat) narrative initial description? Also, why did you feel the need to post pictures of the thing being described? Does that support Flusser's argument, in a way? So many questions. This was great.
Hey Kevin! So is the image on the cover the "image of that explanation" or is it the image itself? Did Beckett himself generate the circle/dot image on the cover? I guess it doesn't really matter - because in any case it's an image of the explanation of a fictional image. That is so cool - thank you for providing me with an example of that convoluted concept! Anyway, do you think Flusser would have something to say about the fact that it is a fictional image? Is it in the synthesis of an imagined (rather than imaginal) surface with its linear explanation that the dichotomy is undermined?
ReplyDelete